首页> 外文学位 >Kant's Libertarianism and Its Aftermath: Rereading The Conflict of the Faculties, Rethinking Hegel, Arendt, and Habermas
【24h】

Kant's Libertarianism and Its Aftermath: Rereading The Conflict of the Faculties, Rethinking Hegel, Arendt, and Habermas

机译:康德的自由主义及其后果:重读各系的冲突,重新思考黑格尔,阿伦特和哈贝马斯

获取原文
获取原文并翻译 | 示例

摘要

Though Immanuel Kant has traditionally been read as an Enlightenment libertarian, most commentators have not counted him among the political radicals of the Enlightenment era. In this dissertation, I propose and defend an original reading of Kant's late treatise Der Streit der Fakultaten (The Conflict of the Faculties) which aims to show that he should in fact count among the radical libertarians of the Enlightenment era whose conception of libertarianism have clear socialist implications. I then propose to use the form of The Conflict of the Faculties as I reconstruct it to interrogate the ethical-political thought of three very different post-Kantians, namely, G. W. F. Hegel, Hannah Arendt, and Jurgen Habermas.;Chapter 1 lays out the object, scope, method, and normative standpoint of the study. Here I propose that we read Kant's The Conflict of the Faculties as a systematically connected exposition of what I call his metapolitics. This is a term that I introduce to characterize the difference between a major treatise on politics such as Kant's Rechtslehre (Doctrine of Right) and a minor one such as The Conflict of the Faculties. I define a metapolitical doctrine as that part of a philosophical system which treats of questions left unaddressed by the major political treatise. There are three such questions: (i) What are the rights and obligations of philosophy in the political public sphere (what I call the intellectual-political conflict of the faculties)? (ii) What are the methodological rights of philosophy to intervene in domains of knowledge considered to be the exclusive property of neighboring humanistic disciplines that happen to also play an ideological function in the service of the state (what I call the methodological-political conflict of the faculties)? And (iii) What are the ultimate moral ends of political life and why (what I call the ethical-political conflict of the faculties)? Taken together, answers to these three questions constitute what I call a philosopher's metapolitics or metapolitical doctrine. I contend here that in addition to being a fruitful way to inquire into the politics of the thinkers under study in this dissertation, this may also be a productive avenue of systematic inquiry into the politics of other philosophers, belonging to different historical epochs and traditions. Chapter 1 concludes with a normative defense of libertarian socialism as the most appropriate metapolitical doctrine.;In Chapter 2 the dissertation reconstructs Kant's metapolitics by way of recovering his answers to the three conflicts of the faculties and then goes on to assess it. Kant's metapolitics consists of three pillars: (i) institutionalized rational dissent (his answer to the intellectual-political conflict), (ii) a principled defense of the rights of practical philosophy (his answer to the methodological-political conflict), and (iii) libertarian republicanism (his answer to the ethical-political conflict). Chapters 3, 4, and 5 of the dissertation reconstruct the answers to the same set of three questions of Hegel, Arendt and Habermas, respectively. I find that Hegel's answer to the three conflicts of the faculties are (i) Staatsphilosophie (state philosophy) (his answer to the first conflict), (ii) a defense of the rights of speculative philosophy (his answer to the second conflict), and (iii) technocratic corporatism (his answer to the third conflict). Arendt's metapolitical triad in turn consists of (i) men of letters' anticonformism (her answer to the first conflict); (ii) a defense of the rights of political theory (her answer the second conflict); and (iii) the aristocratic council system (her answer to the third conflict). Finally, Habermas's metapolitical triad is based on the following three pillars: (i) universal public intellectualism (his answer to the first conflict); (ii) critical social science and postmetaphyiscal philosophy (his answers to the second conflict); and (iii) deliberative democracy (his answer to the third conflict). In each case, after the exposition of the answers, I provide a critical assessment of each of the metapolitical doctrines that they constitute. I find that Kant's metapolitical doctrine is the closest to the libertarian-socialist metapolitics I defend in Chapter 1, whereas Hegel's is directly opposed to it.;The metapolitics of Arendt and Habermas are more complicated. I find that early Habermas was the closest to the spirit of Enlightenment humanism and libertarian socialism in all the important domains: political economy, philosophical anthropology, and cultural politics. However, after the shift to the communicative paradigm which begins around the time of his Christian Gauss lecture (1970/71), Habermas's commitment to libertarian socialist or Enlightenment humanist positions continues to remain strong only in German cultural politics, whereas it is significantly weakened if not altogether abandoned in the domains of political economy and philosophical anthropology. (Abstract shortened by ProQuest.).
机译:尽管依曼纽尔·康德(Immanuel Kant)在传统上被视为启蒙运动的自由主义者,但大多数评论家并未将他视为启蒙运动时代的政治激进分子。在这篇论文中,我提出并捍卫了康德已故专着《院系冲突》的原始读本,该论文旨在表明他实际上应该属于启蒙时代激进的自由主义者,他们对自由主义的观念有清晰的认识。社会主义的含义。然后,我建议使用“学院冲突”的形式来重构它,以询问三种截然不同的后康德主义者,即GWF黑格尔,汉娜·阿伦特和尤尔根·哈贝马斯的伦理政治思想。第一章列出了研究的目的,范围,方法和规范立场。在这里,我建议我们将康德的《学院的冲突》读作是我所说的他的元政治学的系统关联的论述。我用这个术语来描述主要的政治论文(例如康德的权利学说)和次要的论文(例如《学院的冲突》)之间的区别。我将超政治学定义为哲学体系的一部分,该体系处理主要政治论文未解决的问题。存在三个这样的问题:(i)哲学在政治公共领域中的权利和义务是什么(我称之为各学院的思想政治冲突)? (ii)干预知识领域的哲学的方法论权利是什么,这些知识领域被认为是相邻的人文学科的专有财产,而这些知识恰巧也在为国家服务的过程中发挥着意识形态的作用(我称之为“方法论-政治冲突”)。院系)? (iii)政治生活的最终道德终点是什么?为什么(我称这是学院的伦理政治冲突)?综上所述,对这三个问题的回答构成了我所谓的哲学家的元政治学或元政治学说。我在这里主张,除了作为研究本文研究的思想家的政治的一种富有成果的方式之外,这还可能是系统地探究属于不同历史时代和传统的其他哲学家的政治的一条有效途径。第一章以对自由主义者社会主义的规范性辩护作为最合适的元政治学说进行了总结;在第二章中,论文通过恢复康德对系的三个冲突的答案来重构康德的元政治学,然后继续对其进行评估。康德的元政治学包括三个支柱:(i)制度化的理性异议(他对知识政治冲突的回答),(ii)对实践哲学权利的原则性辩护(他对方法论政治冲突的回答),和(iii )自由主义者的共和主义(他对伦理政治冲突的回答)。论文的第三章,第四章和第五章分别重构了对黑格尔,阿伦特和哈贝马斯三个问题的回答。我发现黑格尔对这三个系的冲突的回答是(i)国家哲学(他对第一个冲突的回答),(ii)对投机哲学权利的辩护(他对第二个冲突的回答), (iii)技术官僚主义(他对第三次冲突的回答)。反过来,阿伦特的元政治三合会由(i)信使们的反传统主义者(她对第一次冲突的回答)组成; (ii)捍卫政治理论权利(她回答第二个冲突); (iii)贵族议会制度(她对第三次冲突的回答)。最后,哈贝马斯的元政治三合会基于以下三个支柱:(i)普遍的公共知识分子(他对第一次冲突的回答); (ii)批判性社会科学和后哲学哲学(他对第二次冲突的回答); (iii)协商民主(他对第三次冲突的回答)。在每种情况下,在给出答案后,我都会对它们构成的每个元政治学说进行严格的评估。我发现康德的元政治学说与我在第一章中捍卫的自由主义者-社会主义元政治学最接近,而黑格尔的则直接相反。阿伦特和哈贝马斯的元政治学更为复杂。我发现早期哈贝马斯在所有重要领域(政治经济学,哲学人类学和文化政治)最接近于启蒙主义的人道主义和自由主义社会主义精神。但是,在从基督教高斯讲座(1970/71)左右开始转向交往范式之后,哈贝马斯对自由主义者的社会主义或启蒙主义的人本主义立场的承诺仅在德国文化政治中仍然坚强,即使在政治经济学和哲学人类学领域没有被完全抛弃,它也会被大大削弱。 (摘要由ProQuest缩短。)。

著录项

  • 作者

    Carrabregu, Gent.;

  • 作者单位

    Northwestern University.;

  • 授予单位 Northwestern University.;
  • 学科 Political science.;Philosophy.
  • 学位 Ph.D.
  • 年度 2018
  • 页码 638 p.
  • 总页数 638
  • 原文格式 PDF
  • 正文语种 eng
  • 中图分类
  • 关键词

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号