首页> 外文期刊>Suid-Afrikaanse Tydskrif vir Natuurwetenskap en Tegnologie >Transcending logic: the difference between contradiction and antinomy
【24h】

Transcending logic: the difference between contradiction and antinomy

机译:超越逻辑:矛盾与对立的区别

获取原文
           

摘要

Philosophy and all the academic disciplines are sensitive to the aim of sound reasoning – except for the dialectical tradition which sanctions contradictions and antinomies (Heraclitus, Nicolas of Cusa, Hegel, Marx, Vaihinger, Simmel, Rex, and Dahrendorf). A brief overview is presented of conflicting theoretical stances within the various academic disciplines before an assessment is given of the positive and negative meaning of ‘reductionism.' Against the background of historical lines of development the multiple terms employed in this context are mentioned and eventually positioned within the context of the normativity holding for logical thinking. It is argued that the logical contrary between logical and illogical serves as the foundation of other normative contraries, such as legal and illegal and moral and immoral. Through the discovery of irrational numbers the initial Pythagorean conviction that everything is number reverted to a geometrical perspective that generated a static metaphysics of being which challenged the ideas of plurality and motion. This development uncovered the problem of primitive terms in scientific discourse as an alternative for those theoretical attempts aimed at reducing whatever there is to one single mode of explanation. Zeno's paradoxes are used to demonstrate an alternative understanding of the difference between the potential and the actual infinite as well as the nature of (theoretical) antinomies. It is argued that genuine antinomies are inter-modal in nature (such as is found in the attempt to reduce movement to static positions in space) and therefore differ from logical contradictions (such as a ‘square circle' which merely confuses two figures within one modal aspect). Although every antinomy does entail logical contradictions, the latter do not necessarily presuppose an antinomy. The implication is that logic itself has an ontic foundation – as is seen from the nature of the principle of sufficient reason (ground) and the principle of the excluded antinomy – and therefore only acquires meaning on the basis of a non-reductionist ontology. When the method of immanent critique unveils genuine antinomies, the way is opened for meaningful intellectual interaction between different philosophical stances. In distinguishing between contradiction and antinomy philosophers are actually challenged to contemplate the implications of a non-reductionist ontology, such as avoiding the stance of monistic isms.?
机译:哲学和所有学术学科都对合理推理的目标敏感-制裁矛盾和对立的辩证传统(赫拉克利特,库萨的尼古拉斯,黑格尔,马克思,维辛格,西梅尔,雷克斯和达伦多夫)除外。在对“还原论”的正面和负面含义进行评估之前,简要概述了各个学术领域内相互矛盾的理论立场。在历史发展路线的背景下,提到了在此上下文中使用的多个术语,这些术语最终被定位在逻辑思维的规范规范的上下文中。有人认为,逻辑与非逻辑之间的逻辑对立是其他规范矛盾的基础,例如法律与非法,道德与不道德。通过发现无理数,毕达哥拉斯最初的信念是,一切都是数,因此恢复了几何观点,从而产生了静态的形而上学,这对多元论和运动学提出了挑战。这一发展揭示了科学话语中原始术语的问题,作为那些旨在将一切简化为一种单一解释模式的理论尝试的替代方案。芝诺悖论用于证明对势与实际无限之间的差异以及(理论上的)对数的性质的另一种理解。有人认为,真正的对数本质上是一种联动模式(例如试图将其减少到空间中的静态位置而发现),因此不同于逻辑矛盾(例如一个“正方形圆”,它只会使两个数字混淆在一起)情态方面)。尽管每种对立都必然包含逻辑上的矛盾,但是后者并不一定以对立为前提。这意味着逻辑本身具有本体论的基础(从充分理由(基础)原理的性质和被排除的对立原则的本质可以看出),因此逻辑仅在非还原论本体论的基础上获得意义。当内在批判的方法揭示出真正的对立面时,便为不同哲学立场之间有意义的智力互动开辟了道路。在区分矛盾和对立性时,哲学家实际上面临着挑战以思考非还原论本体论的涵义,例如避免一元论的立场。

著录项

相似文献

  • 外文文献
  • 中文文献
  • 专利
获取原文

客服邮箱:kefu@zhangqiaokeyan.com

京公网安备:11010802029741号 ICP备案号:京ICP备15016152号-6 六维联合信息科技 (北京) 有限公司©版权所有
  • 客服微信

  • 服务号